Alternate Timelines

What If Socrates Was Never Executed?

Exploring how Western philosophy and intellectual development might have unfolded if Socrates had not been executed in 399 BCE but instead continued teaching and developing his ideas into old age.

The Actual History

In 399 BCE, Socrates—one of the most influential figures in Western philosophy—was put on trial in Athens on charges of "impiety" (asebeia) and "corrupting the youth." After being found guilty by a jury of his fellow citizens, he was sentenced to death by drinking hemlock, a sentence he accepted rather than proposing exile or attempting to escape.

This dramatic end to the 70-year-old philosopher's life came during a turbulent period in Athenian history. The city had recently suffered defeat in the Peloponnesian War (431-404 BCE), followed by the brutal rule of the Thirty Tyrants (404-403 BCE), a pro-Spartan oligarchy that included some of Socrates' former students. Though democracy had been restored by the time of his trial, Athenian society remained deeply divided and suspicious of perceived threats to traditional values and democratic institutions.

Several factors contributed to Socrates' prosecution:

  1. Political Associations: Though not politically active himself, Socrates had been the teacher of controversial figures like Alcibiades (who defected to Sparta during the war) and Critias (a leader of the Thirty Tyrants).

  2. Philosophical Method: His distinctive method of questioning (the "Socratic method") challenged conventional wisdom and authority, often publicly embarrassing prominent Athenians.

  3. Religious Skepticism: He claimed to be guided by a personal "daimonion" (divine sign) and questioned traditional religious narratives, raising suspicions of impiety in a society where religion and civic identity were deeply intertwined.

  4. Democratic Tensions: His criticisms of democratic practices and apparent preference for meritocracy over sortition (selection by lot) made him suspect in recently restored democratic Athens.

Socrates' trial and execution had profound consequences for Western philosophy:

  • It transformed Socrates from a controversial local figure into a philosophical martyr whose death symbolized the conflict between the philosopher and society.

  • It deeply influenced his student Plato, whose dialogues not only preserved Socrates' ideas but developed them in new directions, particularly in his middle and late periods when Plato's own voice became more distinct from his teacher's.

  • It established a paradigm of the philosopher as someone willing to die for truth rather than compromise principles, influencing how philosophy was conceived and practiced.

  • It contributed to Plato's skepticism about democracy and his development of alternative political models in works like "The Republic."

Socrates himself left no writings; our knowledge of his ideas comes primarily through the works of others, especially Plato's dialogues. The early Platonic dialogues are generally considered to represent Socrates' historical views more accurately, while the middle and late dialogues increasingly reflect Plato's own philosophical development.

The historical Socrates appears to have focused on ethical questions rather than natural philosophy or metaphysics, employing his method of questioning to expose contradictions in his interlocutors' beliefs and to seek definitions of virtues like courage, justice, and piety. He claimed to know only that he did not know (Socratic ignorance) while seeking wisdom through dialogue.

This historical context raises an intriguing counterfactual question: What if Socrates had not been executed in 399 BCE? How might Western philosophy—and potentially broader intellectual and cultural development—have unfolded differently if he had continued teaching and developing his ideas into old age?

The Point of Divergence

What if Socrates was never executed? In this alternate timeline, let's imagine that in 399 BCE, events at his trial take a different turn.

Perhaps in this scenario, Socrates—recognizing the genuine threat to his life—modifies his famously defiant defense strategy. While still maintaining his philosophical principles, he addresses the jury's concerns more directly, clarifying his religious views and his commitment to Athens despite his criticisms. He might emphasize his military service to the city in the battles of Potidaea, Delium, and Amphipolis, and more explicitly distance himself from the excesses of former students like Critias and Alcibiades.

Alternatively, the political climate might be slightly different—perhaps key accusers like Anytus have less influence, or supporters of Socrates mobilize more effectively to sway public opinion before the trial. The margin of his conviction was reportedly narrow (about 30 votes out of 500 jurors); a small shift in sentiment could have changed the outcome.

In either case, in this alternate timeline, Socrates is either acquitted or, more likely, convicted but given a lesser penalty such as a fine, which his wealthy supporters like Crito and Plato readily pay. Socrates, now about 70 years old, continues to live and teach in Athens for perhaps another decade or more.

During this extended period, several significant developments occur:

  1. Socrates continues his philosophical investigations, perhaps developing his ideas in new directions as he engages with emerging thinkers.

  2. His relationship with students like Plato evolves differently, with more direct transmission of ideas and possibly more explicit guidance of their intellectual development.

  3. He potentially writes down some of his own thoughts or at least reviews and influences the early written works of disciples like Plato and Xenophon.

  4. He might engage more directly with other philosophical schools, including the developing ideas of Antisthenes (founder of the Cynic school), Aristippus (founder of the Cyrenaic school), and Euclides of Megara.

When Socrates eventually dies of natural causes around 385-380 BCE, he leaves behind a more developed philosophical legacy and a different relationship with his successors than occurred historically.

This seemingly modest change—the survival of one elderly philosopher for an additional decade—creates ripples that significantly alter the development of Western philosophy and potentially broader intellectual and cultural history.

Immediate Aftermath

Philosophical Development

The immediate impact of Socrates' continued life would have been felt in philosophical discourse:

  1. Socratic Method Refinement: Socrates might have further refined his distinctive method of questioning, potentially developing more systematic approaches to different types of philosophical problems.

  2. Ethical Exploration: His investigations into virtue, justice, and the good life might have progressed beyond what we know from the early Platonic dialogues, potentially creating more developed ethical frameworks.

  3. Political Philosophy: His experiences during the trial and its aftermath might have stimulated more explicit political thinking, perhaps developing clearer alternatives to existing Athenian institutions.

  4. Epistemological Questions: His explorations of knowledge and its limits (exemplified by his claim to "know that he does not know") might have evolved into more systematic epistemological inquiries.

Platonic Development

Plato's philosophical evolution would have been significantly altered:

  • Extended Apprenticeship: Instead of being forced to develop his ideas independently after Socrates' death, Plato would have continued learning directly from his mentor, potentially creating a different trajectory for his thought.

  • Dialogic Form: The literary form of Plato's dialogues might have evolved differently, perhaps with more direct input from Socrates about his portrayal or even with Socrates reviewing early works.

  • Theory of Forms: Plato's distinctive metaphysical theory of Forms, which many scholars see as a post-Socratic development, might have emerged differently or been subject to Socratic critique if developed during his lifetime.

  • Academy Foundation: Plato's establishment of the Academy (c. 387 BCE) might have occurred with Socrates still alive, potentially creating a different institutional character with the older philosopher's input or even participation.

Intellectual Community

The broader Athenian intellectual community would have been affected:

  • Socratic Circle: The diverse group of thinkers around Socrates might have maintained more cohesion rather than splintering into distinct schools, potentially creating more cross-fertilization of ideas.

  • Rival Schools: The development of philosophical approaches by other Socratic students like Antisthenes (Cynicism) and Aristippus (Cyrenaicism) might have occurred in more direct dialogue with Socrates, potentially creating different philosophical positions.

  • Xenophon's Writings: Xenophon's accounts of Socrates, written historically from exile, might have been composed differently with continued access to his teacher, potentially providing a different complementary perspective to Plato's.

  • Intellectual Reputation: Socrates' survival might have altered Athens' intellectual reputation, potentially reducing the perception of the city as hostile to philosophy that developed after his execution.

Athenian Society

The social and political context would have been subtly transformed:

  • Democratic Practice: Socrates' continued questioning of political assumptions might have influenced Athenian democratic discourse, potentially creating more philosophical reflection on governance during a formative period.

  • Educational Approaches: His educational methods might have influenced more Athenian youth, potentially creating a larger cohort of philosophically trained citizens in the next generation.

  • Religious Attitudes: His survival might have indicated greater Athenian religious tolerance, potentially creating space for more open philosophical discussion of religious questions.

  • Legal Precedent: The trial's outcome (acquittal or lesser penalty) might have established different legal precedents regarding free speech and religious conformity, potentially influencing subsequent cases.

Long-term Impact

Philosophical Traditions

Over centuries, the development of philosophical traditions might have followed different paths:

  • Socratic Schools: The various philosophical schools that claimed Socratic heritage (Platonic, Cynic, Cyrenaic, Megarian) might have developed with more direct Socratic influence, potentially creating different philosophical positions and relationships between these traditions.

  • Platonic Academy: The character and focus of Plato's Academy might have been established differently with Socrates' input, potentially creating a different institutional legacy for one of the ancient world's most important philosophical schools.

  • Aristotelian Divergence: Aristotle, who historically joined Plato's Academy about 367 BCE (after Socrates' death), might have encountered both Socrates and Plato, potentially creating a different relationship between Aristotelian and Platonic thought.

  • Hellenistic Philosophy: Later traditions like Stoicism and Epicureanism, which developed in dialogue with Socratic ideas, might have engaged with a more complex Socratic legacy, potentially creating different philosophical syntheses.

Intellectual Methods

Approaches to knowledge and inquiry might have evolved differently:

  • Dialectical Tradition: The Socratic dialectical method might have developed more continuously and explicitly, potentially creating stronger traditions of philosophical dialogue and questioning.

  • Written vs. Oral Philosophy: Socrates' attitudes toward writing (which Plato portrays as skeptical in dialogues like the Phaedrus) might have directly influenced decisions about philosophical communication, potentially creating different balances between oral and written transmission.

  • Educational Approaches: Socratic pedagogical methods might have been more systematically developed and transmitted, potentially creating different educational traditions in the ancient world.

  • Interdisciplinary Connections: Socrates' wide-ranging interests might have created different connections between philosophy and other fields like mathematics, medicine, or rhetoric, potentially fostering different interdisciplinary approaches.

Political Philosophy

The development of political thought might have followed different trajectories:

  • Democratic Theory: Socrates' continued engagement with Athenian democracy might have created more developed philosophical reflections on democratic governance, potentially creating different theoretical foundations for democratic thought.

  • Utopian Thinking: Plato's utopian political vision in "The Republic" might have developed differently with continued Socratic input, potentially creating different models of ideal governance in Western political thought.

  • Practical Politics: Socrates' survival might have encouraged more philosopher engagement with practical politics, potentially creating different relationships between philosophical theory and political practice.

  • Citizenship Concepts: Philosophical exploration of citizenship and civic virtue might have developed along different lines, potentially creating different conceptual frameworks for understanding the relationship between individual and community.

Religious and Ethical Thought

Moral and religious philosophy might have evolved from different foundations:

  • Virtue Ethics: The Socratic exploration of virtue might have developed more systematically during his extended life, potentially creating different foundations for virtue ethics traditions.

  • Religious Critique: His nuanced approach to religious questions might have created more sophisticated philosophical engagement with traditional religion, potentially developing different relationships between philosophy and theology.

  • Eudaimonic Theories: Theories of happiness and the good life might have developed along different lines with extended Socratic input, potentially creating different eudaimonic traditions in Western ethics.

  • Moral Psychology: Socratic insights about the relationship between knowledge and virtue might have been developed more fully, potentially creating different understandings of moral psychology and character development.

Scientific Development

The relationship between philosophy and empirical inquiry might have evolved differently:

  • Methodological Approaches: Socratic questioning methods might have been more explicitly applied to natural phenomena, potentially creating different methodological approaches to early scientific investigation.

  • Epistemological Foundations: Socratic reflections on the limits of knowledge might have influenced approaches to empirical certainty, potentially creating different epistemological foundations for scientific inquiry.

  • Institutional Structures: The character of institutions like Plato's Academy and Aristotle's Lyceum might have developed differently, potentially creating different organizational models for intellectual inquiry.

  • Disciplinary Boundaries: The relationship between philosophical and empirical investigation might have been conceptualized differently, potentially creating different disciplinary boundaries between philosophy and emerging sciences.

Cultural Impact

The broader cultural influence of Socratic thought might have followed different patterns:

  • Literary Forms: The dialogue form, historically developed by Plato to represent Socratic conversations, might have evolved differently with Socrates' continued influence, potentially creating different literary traditions for philosophical expression.

  • Dramatic Representations: Socrates as a cultural figure might have been portrayed differently in Athenian drama and later literature, potentially creating different artistic and popular understandings of the philosopher.

  • Intellectual Heroism: Without his martyrdom, the archetype of the philosopher might have developed differently, potentially creating different cultural models of intellectual courage and integrity.

  • Athenian Cultural Legacy: Athens' reputation might have been less associated with philosophical intolerance, potentially creating different narratives about the relationship between Athenian democracy and intellectual freedom.

Medieval Transmission

The preservation and interpretation of Socratic ideas during the medieval period might have followed different paths:

  • Textual Corpus: A potentially larger or different corpus of Socratic-influenced texts might have been available for transmission to the medieval period, potentially creating different foundations for medieval philosophical engagement.

  • Islamic Reception: Islamic philosophers like Al-Farabi and Averroes, who engaged deeply with Greek philosophy, might have encountered a different Platonic tradition, potentially creating different Islamic interpretations of Socratic thought.

  • Christian Synthesis: Christian thinkers like Augustine and Aquinas might have engaged with a different Socratic-Platonic legacy, potentially creating different syntheses of classical philosophy and Christian theology.

  • Renaissance Recovery: The Renaissance rediscovery of classical thought might have engaged with a different corpus and interpretation of Socratic ideas, potentially creating different humanistic developments.

Expert Opinions

Dr. Elena Pappas, Professor of Ancient Philosophy at the University of Athens, suggests:

"Had Socrates lived another decade or more, the most profound impact would have been on the development of Plato's thought. The traditional view divides Plato's dialogues into early, middle, and late periods, with the early dialogues considered more faithful representations of the historical Socrates and the middle and late dialogues developing distinctively Platonic ideas like the Theory of Forms. With Socrates living into the 380s BCE, Plato's philosophical development would have occurred with his mentor still present to comment, critique, and influence. The Theory of Forms, if it emerged at all, might have developed very differently under direct Socratic scrutiny. Plato's political philosophy, particularly the utopian vision in 'The Republic,' might have been tempered by Socrates' more practical ethical focus. Most significantly, the sharp distinction scholars make between 'Socratic' and 'Platonic' philosophy might never have emerged. Instead of Plato developing his ideas in response to his teacher's martyrdom, we might have seen a more collaborative and gradual evolution of their shared philosophical project. The entire foundation of Western metaphysics might have taken a different form, perhaps remaining more grounded in ethical inquiry rather than expanding into the elaborate metaphysical systems that characterized Platonism and its many derivatives."

Dr. Marcus Antonius, Historian of Classical Athenian Society at the University of Bologna, notes:

"The social and political implications of Socrates' survival would have been significant for Athens during a crucial period of its recovery after the Peloponnesian War. Historically, his execution has been seen as symbolizing a tension between philosophical inquiry and democratic values. His survival might have allowed for a more productive dialogue between philosophical critique and democratic practice during Athens' fourth-century recovery. Socrates might have continued engaging with questions of citizenship, virtue, and governance in ways that could have strengthened rather than opposed democratic institutions. His students might have been more inclined to work within the democratic system rather than proposing radical alternatives like Plato's philosopher-kings. The relationship between intellectual elite and democratic citizenry might have developed along more complementary rather than antagonistic lines. Athens might have developed a more robust tradition of philosophical reflection on democratic practice, potentially creating more resilient democratic institutions. This might have altered Athens' trajectory during the rise of Macedon, potentially creating different responses to Philip II's expansionism. The entire relationship between philosophy and politics in Western thought might have developed along more collaborative rather than confrontational lines, potentially creating different foundations for political philosophy and practice."

Professor Zhang Wei, Comparative Intellectual Historian at Beijing University, observes:

"We must consider how a longer-lived Socrates might have influenced cross-cultural intellectual exchange. The period following Socrates' death saw significant developments in other philosophical traditions, including Confucianism in China with Mencius (c. 372-289 BCE) and various philosophical schools in India. While direct contact between these traditions was limited in this era, they were addressing similar questions about ethics, governance, and human nature through different methodological approaches. A more developed Socratic method and ethical theory might have created different points of comparison and contrast when these traditions eventually encountered each other in later centuries. The dialogical approach of Socrates might have been more systematically developed, potentially creating different frameworks for cross-cultural philosophical dialogue when these traditions eventually met. Additionally, without the dramatic narrative of Socrates' martyrdom, Western philosophical self-understanding might have developed differently, perhaps emphasizing the philosopher as engaged citizen rather than as critic standing outside society. This might have created different dynamics when Western and non-Western philosophical traditions encountered each other, potentially facilitating different types of philosophical exchange and synthesis. The global history of philosophy might have developed with different patterns of influence and dialogue, potentially creating more mutual recognition of diverse approaches to shared philosophical questions."

Further Reading